The tension between legal theory and policy considerations in the general principles of criminal law

JurisdictionSouth Africa
Date15 August 2019
Citation2003 Acta Juridica 1
Pages1-22
Published date15 August 2019
AuthorCR Snyman
Part A
GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF CRIMINAL
LIABLILITY AND SPECIFIC OFFENCES
The tension between legal theory and policy
considerations in the general principles of
criminal law
C R SNYMAN*
University of South Africa
I INTRODUCTION
Law is the expression of an artif‌icial logic, and this is particularly
evident in the f‌ield of substantive criminal law. Rules of law, and
particularly those relating to criminal law, seldom, if ever, consist entirely
of a purely logical application of a premise. There is always a tension
between two forces: namely, f‌irst, abstract theory, adherence to legal
dogma or systematic reasoning; and, secondly, the concrete or practical
demands of social reality, pragmatism or policy considerations.
This tension is largely also a tension between subjectivism and
objectivism. By ‘subjectivism’ is meant the approach to criminal liability
which places the emphasis on the subjective considerations pertaining to
the individual offender, and by ‘objectivism’ the approach which
emphasises the expectation of society that the conduct of individuals
should conform to certain basic standards, in order to ensure that society
operates peacefully and that justice between individuals or between an
individual and the state is upheld.
The purpose of this chapter is to consider some of the most important
points of tension between legal theory and policy considerations within
the framework of the general principles of South African criminal law.
Most topics deal with aspects of the culpability element, because it is in
this element of liability that the debate between subjectivism and
objectivism is particularly evident. Subjectivism often f‌lows from the
*BA LLB (UOVS);LLD (UOVS); Professor of Criminal and Procedural Law, University of
South Africa, Pretoria.
1
2003 Acta Juridica 1
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd
dictates of criminal-law theory, and objectivism often, if not mostly, from
policy considerations. The tension between subjectivism and objectivism
is particularly evident in the rules relating to the defence of provocation.
The recent judgment of the Supreme Court of Appeal in Eadie
1
highlights this tension. Later in this chapter this decision will come under
close scrutiny.
Up to around 1950, subjective considerations pertaining to criminal
liability played a subordinate role in the construction of criminal liability
in South Africa. The subjective test for intention only developed in the
course of the 1950s.
2
From about this period it became clear that the
courts regarded the test for determining intention to be purely subjective:
in murder cases, for example, the question was no longer whether a
reasonable person in the position of the accused would have foreseen that
the act might lead to the victims death, but whether the particular
accused, in the light of all his personal characteristics such as intelligence
or lack thereof, degree of intoxication, any possible degree to which he
might have been provoked, his age and sex, had in fact appreciated the
possibility that death might ensue.
3
II THE INFLUENCE OF THE BOOK BY DE WET AND
SWANEPOEL
The introduction into South African criminal law of an emphasis on
subjective considerations in the construction of criminal liability owes
much to De Wet and Swanepoels textbook on criminal law, and more
particularly De Wets exposition of, and comments on, the general
principles of liability. The f‌irst edition of this work was published in 1949
under the title Strafreg.
4
In expounding the general principles, De Wet
not only consulted writings on Roman and Roman-Dutch law, but was
also strongly inf‌luenced by continental European literature on criminal
law. He relied extensively on German authors such as Von Liszt-Schmidt,
von Hippel and Beling, as well as on Dutch authors such as Zevenbergen,
von Hamel, Pompe and Vos.
5
These authors belonged to a school, later to be referred to as the
so-called classical school, which was very inf‌luential during the latter
half of the nineteenth century and at the beginning of the twentieth
century.
6
According to this classical school, a sharp distinction is made
1
2002 (1) SACR 683 (SCA).
2
See, for example, R v Huebsch 1953(2) SA 561 (A) at 567; R v Du Randt 1954 (1) SA 313
(A); R v Nsele 1955 (2) SA 145 (A).
3
See, for example, S v Mini 1963 (3) SA 188 (A); S v De Bruyn 1968 (4) SA 498 (A) at
5078; S v Sigwahla 1967 (4) SA 566 (A) 570.
4
J C de Wetand H L Swanepoel Strafreg (1949).
5
De Wetand Swanepoel (n 4) 156.
6
H-H Jescheck Lehrbuch des Strafrechts Allgemeiner Teil5ed (1996) 2013.
2CRIMINAL JUSTICE IN A NEW SOCIETY
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT