Towards a framework for understanding constitutional deference

Pages445-470
Date01 January 2010
DOI10.10520/EJC153235
Published date01 January 2010
AuthorKirsty Mclean
Towards a framework for understanding
constitutional deference
Kirsty Mclean
*
Introduction
This article endeavours to construct a framework for understanding the concept
of constitutional deference. Much has been written about deference in the past
two decades, and this article attempts to piece together the skeleton for a better
understanding and the beginning of a dialogue over the kinds of values which
ought to inform the South African courts’ approach to constitutional deference.
What this article is not is a normative argument about the courts’ approach to
executive and legislative decision-making. Such an argument needs to be
premised upon a particular conception of democracy and the state – an approach
which is not uncontested in the text of the Constitution
1
– and which is beyond the
scope of what is attempted here.
Instead, what this article does seek to do is to provide the tools for a dialogue
for what is termed ‘constitutional deference’, that is, an approach to deference
rooted in our constitutional democracy and our courts’ approach to adjudication.
The article thus seeks to create a framework for an understanding of constitutional
deference which will illuminate the courts’ approach to judicial decision-making.
While the framework is intended to be applicable to the adjudication of all
disputes, this article selects the adjudication of socio-economic rights by the
Constitutional Court as an example of how this framework could usefully
illuminate the approach of the courts to executive and legislative decision-making.
The article is structured in two main parts. The first part provides a framework
for the understanding of constitutional deference as consisting of three,
sometimes competing, considerations which underpin a particular court’s
approach. In the second part, this framework is applied to an examination of the
adjudication of socio-economic rights by the Constitutional Court.
*
I would like to thank Cora Hoexter, Redson Kapindu and the anonymous referees for comments on
earlier drafts of this article. This article is derived in large part from the book McLean Constitutional
deference, courts and socio-economic rights in South Africa (2009).
1
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 1996.
(2010) 25 SAPL446
Framework for understanding constitutional deference
There are a number of reasons why courts defer to executive and legislative
decision-making. These can be grouped together into three intersecting principles,
namely, the court’s views on the democratically legitimate role of a court in a
constitutional democracy, the court’s views on its appropriate role given its
institutional limitations, and the nature of the dispute before a court. Together,
these three principles constitute a particular court’s approach to deference. These
three principles are discussed separately below.
Principles of democracy
The first aspect making up a court’s approach to constitutional deference relates
to its understanding of the institutional independence or interdependence of the
three branches of government, in particular, the role of the courts in a democracy
when engaged in the process of judicial review. This is by far the most important
normative factor underpinning constitutional deference, and the approach taken
by courts on this issue often colours the approach of the courts to the other two
principles. This issue has been described by Jeffrey Jowell as one of
‘constitutional competence’, involving ‘a normative assessment of the proper role
of institutions in a democracy’.
2
The democratic legitimacy of judicial review has been the subject of intense
academic debate, both historically and currently.
3
It is important to note, at the
outset, that this discussion of the debate focuses on whether the institutional
practice of judicial review is, in itself, democratic, and not on the efficacy of the
protection of rights through a system of judicial review. That is a separate question.
4
Neither does this discussion consider the political objections to a rights-based
discourse which argues that a rights-discourse impoverishes our conception of
society and leads to a preoccupation of the individual with his or her rights, rather
than a more group-based approach to rights.
5
The argument that judicial review is
a preferable or even a necessary means to ensure adequate protection of
constitutional rights does not affect the question of the democratic legitimacy of
2
Jowell ‘Of vires and vacuums: The constitutional context of judicial review’ in Forsyth (ed) Judicial
review and the constitution (2000) 327 at 330. Jowell’s argument is set out in relation to
administrative judicial review, but is nevertheless applicable to constitutional review.
3
For a good overview of this debate in the US, see Friedman ‘The birth of an academic obsession:
The history of the countermajoritarian difficulty’ (2002) 112 Yale LJ 153.
4
See Sadurski ‘Judicial review and the protection of constitutional rights’ (2002) 22 Oxford Journal
of Legal Studies 275 at 276.
5
See, eg, Tushnet ‘An essay on rights’ (1984) 62 Texas LR 1363 at 1384-1394; Waldron ‘Nonsense
upon stilts? – a reply’ in Waldron (ed) Nonsense upon stilts: Bentham, Burke and Marx on the rights
of man (1987) 151 at 183-190; and Mouffe ‘Hegemony and new political subjects: Toward a new
concept of democracy’ in Nelson and Grossberg (eds) Marxism and the interpretation of culture
(1988) 89 at 100.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT