The role of moral equality in legal argument

JurisdictionSouth Africa
Pages18-43
Published date15 August 2019
Date15 August 2019
Citation2004 Acta Juridica 18
AuthorStephen Guest
The role of moral equality in legal argument
STEPHEN GUEST*
University College London
I LAW AS A FORM OF MORAL ARGUMENT
What is an ‘analysis’ of the nature of law? Let us suppose that it means that
we have to f‌ind some convention amongst us that determines what
amounts to correct or incorrect understandings of law. It would follow
that we should regard something as law just because people – perhaps a
signif‌icant group of people – accepted it as law, for this is what
determination by convention means.
Note that this method would not help us in analysing morality. Murder
is not murder, or wrong, simply because 100% of people believe it is. So a
conventional account of murder is not possible: in fact, the very last
reason we would offer to say murder was wrong is that everyone thought
it was wrong. In justifying our condemnation of murder we would most
likely give as reasons, ‘a right to live’, ‘the wrongness of causing pain’ or
‘the sanctity of life’ and so on, but not: ‘100% of people think it wrong’. If
we did cite the beliefs of others as the major reason for our belief we
would merely be parroting the views of others – for example, like saying
‘murder is wrong because my father said so’.
People share moral views, true, but we do not think that they hold
genuine moral convictions unless they have formed their view indepen-
dently ‘for themselves’. Given that we share so many moral convictions,
it is not surprising that linguistic conventions have arisen expressing our
shared views – about murder, for example. And so, by convention,
‘murder’ is the word we refer to correctly when contemplating an
intentional killing motivated by personal material gain. (In other
countries, there are different linguistic conventions to express exactly the
same idea.) But it does not follow that the linguistic convention
determines correct understanding, or that it determines the correct set of
reasons that justify thinking this case to be murder. We can only say that
there is a ‘common understanding’ that murder is wrong, and this means
that each person independently holds a conviction that murder is wrong.
*Professor of Legal Philosophy, University College London. I would like to acknowledge
the helpful comments made at the conference by other participants, as well as those of the
participants in the Dworkin Colloquia in Legal and Social Philosophy at UCL one week
earlier, at which this paper was f‌irst presented. In particular,I should thank Ronald Dworkin of
course, Saladin Meckled-Garcia who introduced the paper, Octavio Ferraz, GeorgeLetsas, Riz
Mokal, Eva Pils, and Emmanuel Voyiakis. I would particularly thank Dick Posner who gave
me helpful and detailed comments but added, ‘It is an admirably clear statement of a point of
view with which, as you know, I disagree.’I am also grateful to Ratna Reuben who has made
helpful suggestions in correspondence and discussions.
18
2004 Acta Juridica 18
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd
Not all understandings are held in common with others. Indeed, some
interesting and attractive understandings are not. We can invoke standard
conventions to refer to common understandings in order to challenge
them. That is clear when, for instance, we say of the destruction of stem
cells, ‘I call that murder’ or of some forms of euthanasia, ‘this is not
murder’. More radically, if, for example, someone said that justice is to be
found in the stars, or in desert caves, it would be wrong to say he has said
something contradictory, nor would we suppose he is reporting what is a
common understanding. We might be surprised but, once we learned he
had not made a mistake about the use of words, say, where by ‘justice’he
meant ‘hot gas’, we would wait for his argument.
This is only to say that neither conventional reasons, nor mere
descriptions of common understandings, def‌ine, or ‘analyse’ morality. We
learn from the judgements of others and part of what that means is that
we begin to appreciate appropriate reasons for these judgements. We
learn from our parents, and from others whom we think have special
moral insight, we respond to reasons, we change our minds, we respond
to the reported experiences of others. But what in the end counts is our
correct personal conviction on moral questions.
All this is not, of course, to deny that conventions can be an important
ingredient in our personal moral judgements. It is sometimes right for us
to respect the conventions of others, for example, by removing our shoes
when entering a mosque. In this sort of case, it is not the convention that
determines what we should do, but a duty of respect, or politeness, which
determines our conformity to the particular convention. (Our duty of
respect need not extend to observing all conventions, say, the ‘blooding’
of an initiate to foxhunting.)
We now come to the important question suggested by my title. Given
that law is so similar to morality, why should a different method of
‘analysis’ apply? The question is reasonable because the pervasive impact
of the law on our lives is similar to the demands of morality, most
importantly in the imposition of duties and the conferral of rights. That is
to say, given the likeness between law and morality, there has to be some
good argument to show why the obligations imposed by law should not
ipso facto be moral obligations, and in turn why the doctrine known as
legal positivism should be right.
Practical positivism
Let us imagine some practical purpose would be served by our adopting an
understanding that law was clearly identif‌iable by us all, by adopting a
criterion that specif‌ied laws as the product of a precisely – ‘positively’ –
def‌inable procedure, rather than of moral argument. Such a practical
purpose, if a good purpose, would provide an argument for thinking legal
and moral obligation to be distinct. The invocation of what would be
19
THE ROLE OF MORAL EQUALITY IN LEGAL ARGUMENT
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT