The idea of a legal obligation

JurisdictionSouth Africa
Published date24 December 2019
Date24 December 2019
Citation2019 Acta Juridica 35
AuthorNone
Pages35-56
35
The idea of a legal obligation
NILS JANSEN*
Justinian once dened ‘obligation’ as a vinculum iuris, ie a legal bond
between the debtor and his creditor. Although this concept is still
an aspect of modern legal thinking, it cannot capture all aspects of
obligations in modern law. In fact, the traditional Roman concept
of obligatio does not appropriately account, inter alia, for the modern
principle of freedom of assignments. This essay, therefore, analyses the
history of the concept of obligatio, reecting in particular on the law
of assignment, the law of delict and unjustied enrichment. A result
of this history is that obligations, as far as the creditor’s position is
concerned, are today regarded also as proprietary rights.
I INTRODUCTION
In his early paper on Denition and Theory in Jurisprudence, HLA
Hart emphasised that legal concepts do not refer to objects existing
independently of our legal language. No ‘property’, or ‘contract’, or
‘consideration’, or even a ‘right’ exists independently of our systems
of law. Rather, legal systems are constituted by the conceptual
structure of our legal languages. It follows that legal concepts do
not correspond to the law in the same way as the concept of an
‘apple’ corresponds to apples. The meaning of legal concepts does
not correspond to an independent reality1 because their objects are
institutional facts that are brought about by jurists who coin such
concepts. The realities about which jurists are thinking have thus
been made by former generations of jurists. Young lawyers study
the meaning of those concepts in order to understand what their
law is about. I regard this as an evident insight, which is nevertheless
of great importance for the doctrinal jur ist: on the one hand, those
concepts create Denkzwänge – they set conceptual boundaries to
our legal thinking, and lawyers often nd it dicult to imagine
alternatives. Thus, for a German lawyer, those things that the
common lawyer addresses as a ‘consideration’ simply do not exist.2
* Professor of Civil Law, Institute of Legal History, University of Münster, Germany.
1 HLA Har t Denition and Theory in Jurisprudence (1953) 5.
2 Yet, it would be too simplistic to assume that new elements of legal doctrines
come into the world only with a new word being coined for them. Often, jurists
nd a concept for a legal idea only after having discussed it for some time. Thus,
2019 ACTA 35
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd
36 PRIVATE LAW IN A CHANGING WORLD
On the other hand, like every human institution, such concepts are
not xed for all time. They can be, and sometimes need to be, re-
designed in order to t in with social, economic or legal change.
I think that this basic insight into the nature of legal concepts
is helpful in understanding the idea of a doctrinal, or legal,
‘construction’. Today, constructive approaches to jur isprudence do
not seem to be particularly fashionable. They evoke ideas of alleged
nineteenth-century formalism, or of Begrisjurisprudenz. But such
a view may be misleading. Indeed, Rudolf von Jhering, who gave
powerful expression to the idea of a Constructionsjurisprudenz,3 made
it quite clear that the point of such an approach to legal doctrine
was to understand doctrinal concepts as tools to be designed by
jurists. And, in his later work, Jher ing complemented this basic idea,
showing that the main aspect of a convincing legal construction
was the purpose of the concept being considered.4 If the doctrinal
conception of a concept such as ‘property’, ‘right’, or ‘obligation’ is
to regard it as a construction in this sense of a purposively designed
tool, jurists will assume that its precise contours are not naturally
given. They will ask whether it needs to be improved to perfor m its
function in their legal world appropriately.
A symposium honouring Danie Visser is an ideal occasion to
analyse, with those remarks in mind, the idea of a legal obligation.
Obligations, particularly non-contractual obligations, have been
the focus of Danie’s work, and Danie has never been content
the German Obliegenheiten are much older than the word Obliegenheit’. Yet, even
before they coined the modern concept, jurists were perfectly able to discuss the
relevant ideas in their language; cf on those discussions on contr ibutory negligence,
N Jansen in MSchmoeckel, JRückert & RZimmermann (eds) Histor isch-kritischer
Kommentar zum BGB (2003/2007/2013) §254 [48]. Otherwise, they would not
have been able to think about this idea.
3 Rvon Jhering ‘Unsere Aufgabe’ (1857) 1Jahrbücher für die Dogmatik des heutigen
römischen und deutschen Privatrechts; see also the Introduction to Jhering’s Der Geist
des römischen Rechts auf den verschiedenen Stufen seiner Entwicklung, TeilI 2 ed (1866).
On Jhering’s programme and his theory of a legal construction, seeN Jansen &
M Reimann ‘Begri und Zweck in der Jurisprudenz. Ein Geburtstagsblatt für
Rudolf von Jhering’ (2018) Zeitschrift für Europäisches Privatrecht 89–129, 95–106.
4 Rvon Jhering Der Zweck im Recht volI 2 ed (1884); volII (1883); see Jansen &
Reimann ‘Begri und Zweck’ (n3) 109–12. Jhering was never a Begrisjurist who
would not have teleologically reected the concepts and rules under consideration;
and he never stopped working doctrinally on the Roman heritage. Indeed, with
his last major work, Der Besitzwille. Zugleich eine Kritik der herrschenden juristischen
Methode (Jena 1889), he wanted to give a doctrinal example for his teleological
method: loc cit, ix, 364.
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT