The content and justification of rationality review

Pages346-381
Published date01 January 2010
Date01 January 2010
AuthorAlistair Price
DOI10.10520/EJC153240
The content and justification of rationality
review
Alistair Price
*
1Introduction
It is a general principle of South African constitutional law that every law and every
exercise of public power should not be arbitrary but, instead, should be rational.
1
This
principle, developed by the Constitutional Court in a series of judgments,
2
sets
rationality or non-arbitrariness as a necessary condition that every law or act of all
branches and spheres of the state must satisfy in order to be legally valid. It operates
as a minimum standard – a constitutional baseline – that applies even in
circumstances where no fundamental right or other constitutional standard is directly
applicable. By developing this principle, the courts have asserted a significant power,
for they are now able to assess, on substantive grounds, the rationality of every
provision in the statute book and all conduct of the executive, public administration,
and other organs of state.They do so, in general, by deciding whether the law or
*
BBusSc LLB (UCT) BCL (Oxon). Research student, Gonville and Caius College, Cambridge
University. I am very grateful to Michael Bishop, Coel Kirkby, Hannah Woolaver, and the participants
at a seminar on 2009-07-06 at the South African Institute for Advanced Constitutional, Public,
Human Rights and International Law, Johannesburg, for their comments on an earlier draft of this
essay. Any errors are mine alone.
1
Throughout this essay, I refer to this general prohibition on arbitrariness as the ‘rationality principle’
and describe its application by the courts as ‘rationality review’.
2
S v Makwanyane 1995 3 SA 391 (CC) para 156; Prinsloo v Van der Linde 1997 3 SA 1012 (CC)
para 24; New National Party v Government of South Africa 1999 3 SA 191 (CC) paras 19 and 24;
Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of South Africa: In re Ex parte President of South Africa
2000 2 SA 674 (CC) paras 85 and 90; United Democratic Movement v President of South Africa (No
2) 2003 1 SA 495 (CC) para 55; and Affordable Medicines Trust v Minister of Health 2006 3 SA 247
(CC) paras 74-79; Albutt v Centre for the Study of Violence and Reconciliation [2010] ZACC 4 para
49; Poverty Alleviation Network v President of South Africa [2010] ZACC 5 para 65; Law Society of
South Africa v Minister for Transport [2010] ZACC 25 paras 32-39; and Glenister v President of
South Africa [2011] ZACC 6 paras 55-70. For a comparative analysis of Poverty Alleviation Network
and Albutt, see Price ‘Rationality review of legislation and executive decisions’ (2010) 127 SALJ 580-
591. Due to time and spatial constraints, I have been unable to include a discussion of Law Society
of South Africa and Glenister. Fortunately, the reasoning and outcome of those decisions is
consistent with, and in many respects confirms, the arguments advanced below.
The content and justification of rationality review 347
conduct in question is rationally connected to a legitimate government purpose.
3
If
that minimum standard is not met, the law or conduct is unconstitutional. The courts
have held that this power is justified by the rule of law which, by virtue of s 1(c) of the
Constitution, is a founding value of South African law.
4
Without doubt, the uniquely
broad applicability of this rationality principle, and its apparently foundational nature
as an entailment of the rule of law, underline the importance of a sound grasp of its
content and justification.
Michael Bishop has written an insightful and provocative essay exploring
rationality review only as it applies to legislative differentiations between classes of
persons in terms of section 9(1) of the Constitution.
5
For our courts apply that
provision by invalidating legislative differentiations that are irrational or arbitrary.
6
Bishop’s argument has two legs: the first critical; the second constructive. He argues
that the structure of rationality review, and perhaps also the manner in which it has
been applied, ensure that it cannot serve its traditional justifications. He then
proposes an additional justification for the rationality principle, as well as a new
structure for its application, which together, he claims, ‘save’ rationality review. What
follows here is an attempt, in a spirit of collaboration, to evaluate Bishop’s argument.
I do so indirectly, by offering an alternative account of the content and justification of
rationality review that is both broader and narrower than his. It is broader because I
consider rationality review of legislation and exercises of public power generally, not
only of differentiations in terms of section 9(1). It seems to me that this broad
applicability, together with the courts’ view that rationality review is justified by the rule
of law, call for a wider analysis. My account is narrower because it focuses solely on
South African law, whereas Bishop compares rationality review in South Africa and
the United States and draws conclusions that seem to apply equally to both countries.
I am hesitant to follow Bishop down the comparative road for two reasons.
First, rational basis review under the US equal protection clause
7
applies to many
legislative differentiations that in South Africa are tested against the more rigorous
prohibition on unfair discrimination in terms of section 9(3) of the Constitution.
8
For
example, differentiations on grounds of sexual orientation, age, or HIV-status
3
The content of the rationality principle is analysed more closely below, from 7.
4
See, eg, Prinsloo (n 2) para 25; City Council of Pretoria v Walker 1998 2 SA 363 (CC) para 137;
New National Party (n 2) para 24; Pharmaceutical Manufacturers (n 2) para 85; Albutt (n 2) para 49;
and Poverty Alleviation Network (n 2) para 65.
5
Bishop ‘Rationality is dead! Long live rationality! Saving rational basis review’ (2010) 25 SAPL 312.
Section 9(1) provides that ‘Everyone is equal before the law and has the right to equal protection and
benefit of the law.’ Bishop suggests (3) that his conclusions may apply beyond the context of s 9(1).
6
This rule was first established in Prinsloo (n 2) para 24.
7
The relevant part of the Fourteenth Amendment to the US Constitution provides that ‘No State shall
… deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws’.
8
Section 9(3) provides that ‘The state may not unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against anyone
on one or more grounds, including race, gender, sex, pregnancy, marital status, ethnic or social origin,
colour, sexual orientation, age, disability, religion, conscience, belief, culture, language and birth’.
(2010) 25 SAPL348
need merely be rational in the United States,
9
whereas South African courts
assess whether they constitute unfair discrimination. Some of the academic
disapproval of rational basis review in the United States may be partly motivated
by the relative ease with which such differentiations are upheld as constitutional,
because rational, in that country. In South Africa, by contrast, the broader reach
and higher standard of the prohibition on unfair discrimination ensure that many
of these differentiations will not survive constitutional scrutiny, whether or not they
satisfy the rationality principle. Accordingly, rationality review arguably has costs
in the United States that it does not incur in South Africa. Secondly, the
justification of rationality review depends to a significant extent on the manner in
which its evaluative and vague elements are applied by judges in particular cases.
But it is by no means clear that since 1994 South African judges have applied the
rationality principle in a manner identical to US judges. Whatever the record of the
US courts may be, we need not accept Bishop’s claim that the South African
Constitutional Court is guilty of applying the rationality principle in an inappropriate
way. For these two reasons, we should be hesitant to tar rationality review in both
legal systems with the same critical brush.
Having explained the difference between the scope of my account of rationality
review and Bishop’s, I now outline the argument that follows. Part 2 surveys the
different contexts in which the rationality principle applies. I then analyse its content,
drawing attention to some of its characteristics – in particular, the fact that its
application often requires courts to make discretionary judgments – which call for
further explanation and justification. Part 3 takes the first step by analysing the
distinction between reasonableness and rationality in constitutional law. It then
explains the court’s duty to respect, or not to ‘second-guess’, the political autonomy
of the executive and legislature, as well as the idea that judicial scrutiny can vary in
intensity. This part concludes by briefly considering the notion of arbitrariness.
Having explained the content of the rationality principle, I turn to its justification. Part
4 advances some reasons for believing that rationality review is justified in principle,
relying prominently on the idea that its discretionary character is part of its value. Part
5 argues that rationality review is justified in practice, because the Constitutional
Court has, on the whole, applied the rationality principle sensibly. My ultimate
conclusion, then, is that rationality review does not need to be saved.
2 The content of rationality review
2.1 Contexts in which the constitutional principle of rationality
is applicable
The first category of cases in which the rationality principle is applied are those
addressing whether legislative differentiations between classes of persons comply
9
See, for a classic account, Tribe American constitutional law (1988) (2
nd
ed) ch 16.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT