A Sliding Scale of Reasonableness in Judicial Review

JurisdictionSouth Africa
Date15 August 2019
Published date15 August 2019
Pages233-256
AuthorJohannes Chan
A Sliding Scale of Reasonableness in
Judicial Review
JOHANNES CHAN*
University of Hong Kong
I INTRODUCTION
A cardinal principle that has shaped the development of judicial review is
the doctrine of separation of powers. The principle of Wednesbury
unreasonableness, which has been the orthodox position in judicial
review for decades, is heavily inf‌luenced by this doctrine of separation of
powers. Under this doctrine, there is a boundary of administrative
discretion beyond which judicial supervision should not cross, even
though the dividing line is often blurred and the precise boundary keeps
shifting.
1
Thus, Lord Brightman cautioned as follows in Chief Constable of
the North Wales Police v Evans:
2
Judicial review is concerned, not with the decision, but with the decision-
making process. Unless that restriction on the power of the court is observed,
the court will . . . under the guise of preventing the abuse of power, be itself
guilty of usurping power.
Likewise, in the classic statement of Lord Diplock in the seminal case
of Council of Civil Service Unions v Minister for the Civil Service, ‘the reasons
for the decision-maker taking one course rather than another do not
normally involve questions to which, if disputed, the judicial process is
adapted to provide the right answer.’
3
The same approach has been
followed in Hong Kong. In a case challenging the decision of the
Commissioner of Correctional Services to remove racing pages from
newspapers subscribed to by prisoners on racing days, in order to curb
illegal gambling in prison, Litton VP refused to entertain any argument
on the irrationality of the policy and held that ‘competing policy
considerations are not matters which courts of law can properly weigh.
These are matters of value judgment based on priorities which the
decision-maker considers relevant.’
4
* Professor and Dean, Faculty of Law, University of Hong Kong.
1
See Wade& Forysth Administrative Law 9 ed (2004) 362–372.
2
3
[1985] AC 374 at 411.
4
Chim Shing Chung v Commissioner of Correctional Services (1996) 6 HKPLR 313 at 320.
233
2006 Acta Juridica 233
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd
II WEDNESBURY AND MERITS REVIEW
Ironically, the need to enter into a merits review, at least in the extreme
cases, is recognized in the classic statement of Lord Greene in the original
Wednesbury formulation:
5
It is true that discretion must be exercised reasonably. Now what does that
mean? Lawyers familiar with the phraseology used in relation to exercise of
statutory discretions often use the word ‘unreasonable’ in a rather compre-
hensive sense. It has frequently been used and is frequently used as a general
description of the things that must not be done. For instance, a person
entrusted with a discretion must, so to speak, direct himself properly in law.
He must call his own attention to the matters which he is bound to consider.
He must exclude from his consideration matters which are irrelevant to what
he has to consider. If he does not obey those rules, he may truly be said, and
often is said, to be acting ‘unreasonably’. Similarly, there may be something so
absurd that no sensible person could ever dream that it lay within the powers
of the authority. Warrington LJ in Short v Poole Corporation gave the example
of the red-haired teacher, dismissed because she had red hair. This is
unreasonable in one sense. In another it is taking into consideration
extraneous matters. It is so unreasonable that it might almost be described as
being done in bad faith; and, in fact, all these things run into one another.
The essence that runs through this passage is that any discretionary
power must be exercised in a way that is consistent with the reason for
the power being conferred in the f‌irst place. Rationality is an objective
standard and embodies the possibility of the co-existence of more than
one view. It has to be determined within the context of the statutory
scheme that confers the discretion. Seen in this context, it is almost
impossible to determine rationality without at the same time considering
the merits of the decision. The court may not substitute its own decision
for that of the executive, but this is not the same as saying that the court
should completely leave the weighing of competing values to the
executive without at least satisfying itself in appropriate circumstances
that due weight has been accorded to relevant interests and factors.
6
Hence, it is misleading to characterize judicial review as concerning only
the decision-making process and not the decision itself. Indeed, even in
the most extreme formulation of the Wednesbury unreasonableness test,
such as a decision ‘so absurd that no sensible person could ever dream that
it lay within the powers of the authority’,
7
or a decision ‘so outrageous in
its def‌iance of logic or of accepted moral standards that no sensible person
5
Associated Provincial Picture Houses Ltd v Wednesbury Corporation [1948] 1 KB 223 at 229.
6
See R (Daly) v Secretary of State for Home Department [2001] 2 AC 532 at 547 per Lord
Steyn.
7
Associated Provincial PictureHouses Ltd v Wednesbury Corporation [1948] 1 KB 223 at 229 per
Lord Greene MR.
234 COMPARING ADMINISTRATIVE JUSTICE ACROSS THE COMMONWEALTH
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT