A provocative response to subjectivity in the criminal law

JurisdictionSouth Africa
Published date15 August 2019
Date15 August 2019
Pages23-47
AuthorJonathan Burchell
A provocative response to subjectivity in the
criminal law
JONATHAN BURCHELL*
University of Cape Town
I THE BACKGROUND
The criminal law is riddled with numerous value-laden judgements:
distinctions between the extent of criminal liability attaching to acts
rather than omissions; between the factual and the legal chain linking
conduct and consequence; between the criminal results of prohibited acts
perpetrated under pathological, as opposed to non-pathological, inf‌lu-
ences; between criminality of intentional as opposed to negligent
conduct; between the degree of liability of perpetrators and accessories;
and between completed and inchoate offences. Value-laden judgements
implicit in these decisions leave inherent scope for discretion and
discretion, of course, permits an essential balancing of interests.
Tension between descriptive and normative rules in the criminal law is
no more apparent than in the attitude of the courts to the predicament of
a killing that was provoked.
1
Should the law even countenance provoca-
tion as a defence to criminal liability, as opposed to recognising that
provocation could serve to mitigate the severity of sentence? Should the
law adopt a middle course by acknowledging some limited hybrid form of
defence whereby conduct, which would otherwise have been suff‌icient
to constitute full-blown criminal conduct, might be ‘partially excused’, if
perpetrated under severe provocation? Should the law give the defence its
fullest possible legal relevance by concluding that provocation, of
suff‌icient degree, could completely negate criminal liability? If provoca-
tion raises an issue of criminal capacity, then is this capacity judged
entirely subjectively or is there an objective, normative dimension to the
capacity inquiry?
2
*BA LLB (Natal) LLM Diploma in Comparative Legal Studies (Cantab) PhD (Wits),
Professor of Criminal Law, University of Cape Town.
1
The term ‘provocation’ in this chapter is used as covering its broader relative ‘emotional
stress’. On the theoretical distinction between the two concepts, see J Burchell and J Milton
Principles of Criminal Law 2ed (1997, revised reprint 2002) 288 where it is suggested that the
origin of the stressful condition should not matter in principle, but could effect the intensity or
severity of the ultimate condition.
2
Professor C R Snyman in this very volume of Acta Juridica argues that the judgment of
Navsa JA in S v Eadie 2002 (1) SACR 683 (SCA) is a ‘triumph for the policy approach to
provocation, and heralds a defeat of the purely theoretical approach to this defence’ (at 14).
According to Snyman, at the end of the day, the defence of provocation after Eadie exists in
name only because the court equates the defence in its non-pathological form with the defence
23
2003 Acta Juridica 23
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd
At some stage or other in the development of the South African rules
relating to provocation, the courts have in fact f‌lirted with virtually the
full spectrum of apparent solutions to the dilemma. One solution, which
understandably has not openly been countenanced, for obvious constitu-
tional reasons, is tampering with the sacrosanct presumption of inno-
cence.
3
Another extreme solution always waiting in the wings is, of
course, legislative reform of the common law but, as yet, the South
African criminal law has not taken this route.
Roman and Roman-Dutch law did not regard anger, jealousy or other
emotions as an excuse for any criminal conduct but only as factors, which
might mitigate sentence, if these emotions were justif‌ied by provocation.
The Rumpff Commission of Inquiry into Responsibility of Mentally
Deranged Persons and Related Matters in 1967, although it recom-
mended that an examination of the cognitive and conative functions of
the mind be accommodated within the legal test of criminal capacity, did
not consider that the affective functions of the mind, which regulate
emotions such as hatred, love, and jealousy, should be relevant to criminal
liability,
4
as opposed to punishment.
This sensible approach of the Roman and Roman-Dutch law and the
sage advice of the Rumpff Commission were, however, not heeded by
in its automatism form. It is argued in the present chapter that Snyman has overstated the effect
of Eadie on both these issues.
3
As an exception to the general rule that the prosecution bears the overall burden to prove
the existence of all elements of criminal conduct beyond reasonable doubt, the accused in
South Africa is held to bear the burden of proving, on a balance of probabilities, insanity. This
exception is of dubious constitutional validity but has been endorsed by both the courts and the
legislature (s 78(1A) of the Criminal Procedure Act 51 of 1977, inserted by s 5(b) of Act 68 of
1998). Section 78(1B) of the Criminal Procedure Act, also inserted by the same section of Act
68 of 1998 and which came into operation on 28 February 2002 states that [w]henever the
criminal responsibility of an accused with reference to the commission of an act or omission
which constitutes an offence is in issue, the burden of proof with reference to criminal
responsibility of the accused shall be on the party who raises the issue. If taken out of context,
this loosely-worded section could be invoked to argue that the legislature has, in fact, shifted
the onus of proving lack of criminal responsibility (ie capacity) onto the accused, not only in
cases where insanity is raised by the accused as a defence but also in cases where non-pathological
incapacity is raised as a defence. This conclusion, it is submitted, is not justif‌ied. The amending
legislation is clearly designed to regulate matters relating to pathological mental conditions not
non-pathological conditions, and, furthermore, the original portion of s 78(1), which still stands,
patently uses the phrase criminally responsiblein the context of insanity. It would be
extravagant, and involve an infringement of the fundamental presumption of innocence the
justif‌iability of which has not yet been judicially determined to contend that the legislature
intended to override, impliedly and in one loosely-worded phrase, decades of judicial
precedent supporting placing no more than an evidential burden on an accused who raises
non-pathological incapacity as a defence.
4
Similar sentiments seem to be echoed by the words of Lord Justice-General (Rodger) in
Galbraith v Her Majesty’s Advocate 2001 SCCR 551 (High Court of Justiciary): . . . the law
makes no such allowance for failings and emotions, such as anger and jealousy, to which any
normal person may well be subject from time to time. They do not call for the laws
compassion. Rather, we must master them or face the consequences(para51).
24 CRIMINAL JUSTICE IN A NEW SOCIETY
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT