On the limits of cultural accommodation: KwaZulu-Natal MEC for Education v Pillay

JurisdictionSouth Africa
Published date15 August 2019
Date15 August 2019
Citation2015 Acta Juridica 456
Pages456-494
AuthorOkyerebea Ampofo-Anti
On the limits of cultural accommodation:
KwaZulu-Natal MEC for
Education v Pillay
OKYEREBEA AMPOFO-ANTI* AND MICHAEL BISHOP
In KwaZulu-Natal MEC for Education v Pillay, Chief Justice Langa held that it
constituted unfair discrimination for a public school to prevent a learner from
wearing a nose stud to school, because wearing the stud was a voluntary part of
the learner’s religion and, more importantly, her culture. In this contribution
we consider the limits of this type of cultural accommodation after Pillay by
focusing on two questions: What types of beliefs and practices are ‘‘cultural’’?
And how should courts determine the burdens other must bear to accommo-
date cultural practices? First, we offer preliminary answers to three central
questions that Pillay left unanswered: What is a culture? Who qualif‌ies as a
member of a culture? How do we determine which practices are part of a
culture? Second, we discuss the role and meaning of ‘‘reasonable accommoda-
tion’’and argue that Pillay mistakenly framed it as a balancing test between the
interests of the learner and the school. In doing so, it obscured other important
factors that should be considered.
I INTRODUCTION
To what extent do cultural practices have to be accommodated in public
institutions? This was the question that was placed before the Constitu-
tional Court in MEC for Education: Kwazulu Natal v Pillay (Pillay)
1
which
concerned the right of a learner to wear a nose stud to school. Langa CJ
held for the court that the school was obliged to permit the learner to
wear her nose stud.
In this contribution, we explore the likely limits of the type of cultural
accommodation presaged in Pillay. Will learners at schools who claim to
be part of Punk culture demand their right to tattoos, f‌lesh tunnels and
Mohawks? Can an employee who is fanatical about Kaizer Chiefs claim
that he is a member of Kaizer Chiefs culture and that he is therefore
entitled to time off from work to attend the Chief v Pirates derby, a major
‘cultural’ festival? Can a recent German immigrant to Cape Town claim
exemption from by-laws to slaughter a cow in his backyard because he
* Partner, Webber Wentzel; Attorney of the High Court of South Africa; LLB LLM
(Pretoria).
Counsel, Constitutional Litigation Unit, Legal Resources Centre; Honorary Research
Associate, University of Cape Town; Member of the Cape Bar; BALLB LLM (Pretoria) LLM
(Columbia).
1
456
2015 Acta Juridica 456
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd
considers himself part of Zulu culture? And can an employer be required
to accommodate a person’s cultural practice of coming to work dressed in
a loincloth?
In short, does the approach to cultural accommodation in Pillay entitle
a person to make up a culture, claim membership of it, assert that a
practice that she ‘sincerely believes’ in is part of that culture, and then
demand that she be accommodated?
This is not merely another ‘parade of horribles’.
2
The justif‌ications for
protection of cultural practices that Langa CJ proffers in Pillay could be
read to protect an individual right to identity that entitles a ‘reasonable
accommodation’ for any practice a person believes is important to her
identity. One commentator has explained his fears as follows:
One wonders how and whether a belief sheltered by, say, iconoclastic or
eccentric expressions of individual will, but nonetheless a ‘belief’, would be
analysed? What weight is placed on the balancing scales where uniforms are
weighed not against religious or cultural beliefs and membership (which the
cases show can marshal signif‌icant social arguments for their respect) but
against what may seem merely idiosyncratic whims or expressions of pique,
adolescent rebellion or ego? Say, a clerk at the Constitutional Court who
sports a Mohawk and goes barefoot with or without wearing a kilt. If the test
here is largely subjective (as it would appear to be with both religion and now
culture after Pillay), why should we treat the non-religious, non-cultural
individual claim for respect differently than claims that are at bottom commu-
nal, but which the Court treats as individual forms of expressive conduct?
3
This contribution avoids the larger moral question posed by this hypo-
thetical: Should the law accommodate non-cultural, non-religious claims
for protection of practices that are important to a person’s identity?
4
Instead, it argues that Pillay did not establish an open season for
individual claims of ‘identity accommodation’. Properly understood,
Pillay creates several safety valves that will allow courts in the future to
prevent absurd or unrealistic claims for cultural accommodation. It
2
Pillay (n 1) para 94, quoting Employment Division, Department of Human Resources of Oregon,
et al v Smith, et al 494 US 872 (1990) 902 (O’Connor J, dissenting).
3
I Benson ‘The case for religious inclusivism and the judicial recognition of religious
associational rights:A response to Lenta’ (2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 295 at 307–8.
4
One of the authors has addressed that question elsewhere and argued that we should
protect such claims of identity (although we should not protect ‘merely idiosyncratic whims or
expressions of pique, adolescent rebellion or ego’). See M Bishop A Story Like the Wind:Identity,
Storytelling and Human Rights Law (unpublished LLM thesis, University of Pretoria, 2008). For a
similar argument, with a very different conclusion, see B Leiter Why Tolerate Religion? (2014).
Leiter – whose focus is on whether religion deserves special protection – concludes that it does
not. He reasons that all claims of conscience deserve equal protection but that for practical
reasons about inequality in proving non-religious claims, and the possibility that granting
exemptions will shift burdens to those who have no claim of exemption, no claims of
conscience (religious or non-religious) should be permitted.
457
ON THE LIMITS OF CULTURAL ACCOMMODATION
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd
establishes a principled basis for the protection of culture that is not
limited to traditional understandings of what constitutes a culture, and
allows any group that believes it can justify exemption on those principled
grounds an opportunity to seek to be accommodated.
While Pillay establishes this nuanced framework, it is neither complete
nor perfect. It leaves several important questions about the scope of claims
for cultural accommodation largely unanswered: What is a ‘culture’?
How do we determine cultural membership? Which beliefs or practices
are ‘cultural’? Langa CJ’s judgment also, perhaps unintentionally, estab-
lished a mechanism for the balancing of competing interests that leaves
out important public considerations, and reduces cultural claims entirely
to the subjective positions of the competing parties. We argue that the
rubric of ‘reasonable accommodation’ the court employed, while helpful,
can obscure rather than illuminate the issues at stake. Abetter understand-
ing of the role of reasonable accommodation will prevent cultural
accommodation from being abused while still allowing suff‌icient space
for not only tolerating cultural and religious diversity, but ‘celebrating’it.
5
The contribution is structured as follows. Part II summarises the facts
and f‌indings in Pillay with an emphasis on those issues we consider later in
the paper. Part III addresses the three questions concerning what types of
cultural practices should be protected after Pillay: What is a ‘culture’?
How do we know who are members of a culture? And how do we
determine which practices or beliefs are ‘cultural’? Lastly, in Part IV we
deal with the question of ‘reasonable accommodation’. We contend that
the phrase – which is central to Langa CJ’s analysis in Pillay – misstates the
appropriate test for fairness under the Promotion of Equality and Preven-
tion of Unfair Discrimination Act 4 of 2000 (the Equality Act). Reason-
able accommodation should be treated as an overarching substantive
principle, not a method of analysis.
II PILLAY
During the September holidays in 2004 Ms Pillay permitted her daughter
Sunali to pierce her nose and to insert a small gold nose stud. When Sunali
returned to Durban Girls’ High School (the school) after the holidays, Ms
Pillay was informed that Sunali was not permitted to wear the nose stud.
The school told her that its code of conduct (the Code) restricted
jewellery to one pair of plain earrings and a watch. It asked Ms Pillay to
motivate why Sunali should be exempted from the code of conduct.
Ms Pillay explained to the school that the nose stud held cultural and
religious signif‌icance to the family. The family was of South Indian origin
and according to their culture every woman in the family would have her
5
Pillay (n 1) para 65.
458 A TRANSFORMATIVE JUSTICE:ESSAYS IN HONOUR OF PIUS LANGA
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT