Judge Ackermann and the Jurisprudence of Mourning

JurisdictionSouth Africa
Citation2008 Acta Juridica 219
Published date15 August 2019
Pages219-238
Date15 August 2019
Judge Ackermann and the Jurisprudence
of Mourning
DENNIS M DAVIS*
Cape High Court
When the great Israel Baal Shem Tov saw misfortune threatening the Jews, it
was his custom to go into a certain part of the forest to meditate. There he
would light a f‌ire, say a special prayer, and the miracle would be accomplished
and the misfortune averted.
Later when his disciple, the celebrated Maggid of Mezeritch, had occasion,
for the same reason, to intercede with heaven, he would go to the same place
in the forest and say: ‘‘Master of the Universe, listen! I do not know how to
light the f‌ire, but I am still able to say the prayer.’ And again the miracle
would be accomplished.
Still later, Moshe-Leib of Sassov, in order to save his people once more,
would go into the forest and say: ‘‘I do not know the prayer, but I know the
place and this must be suff‌icient.’’ It was suff‌icient and the miracle was
accomplished.
Then it fell to Israel of Rizhin to overcome misfortune. Sitting in his
armchair, his head in his hands, he spoke to God: ‘‘Iam unable to light the f‌ire
and I do not know the prayer; I cannot even f‌ind the place in the forest. All I
can do is tell the story, and this must be suff‌icient.’’And it was suff‌icient.
It no longer is. The proof is that the threat has not been averted. Perhaps we are no
longer able to tell the story. Could all of us be guilty? Even the survivors? Especially the
survivors?’
1
I INTRODUCTION
Gillian Rose uses the above midrash – which is derived from the work of
Martin Buber and Elie Wiesel – to address the challenges confronting
survivors. Rose contends that survivors would be guilty if they remained
‘self-def‌ined solely as survivors; guilty’ because they would be f‌ixed in ‘a
counter–identif‌ication’:
2
To survive – to live again – demands a new tale: a new prayer to be found, a
new polity to be founded. It demands a willingness to participate in power
and its legitimate violence for the sake of the good.
3
I wish to employ this use of midrash by Rose to interrogate the
concept of transformation of the South African legal system and the
* Judge of the High Court, Cape of Good Hope Provincial Division.
1
G Rose Mourning Becomes the Law (1996) at 99–100.
2
Ibid at 100.
3
Ibid.
219
2008 Acta Juridica 219
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd
manner in which the concept has been implemented in the early
jurisprudence of the Constitutional Court. It is in these early develop-
ments of constitutional jurisprudence that Judge Ackermann played a
critical role.
This paper focuses on the manner, in which the Constitutional Court,
in its early jurisprudence, set the foundations for the ‘transformative’
development of South African private law. The body of private law
which was inherited from apartheid eschewed any recourse to the
concepts adopted in public law. Private lawyers were generally con-
cerned with purity of concept rather than an interrogation of the power
relationships which were ref‌lected, reinforced and reproduced through
those arrangements underpinned by private law. The Constitution
4
promised an end to this insulation of private arrangements sanctioned by
law from judicial scrutiny.
5
These developments posed the possibility of a
public meaning for private law; hence, how did the Court answer this
question? Before engaging in this investigation, it is necessary to refer,
albeit brief‌ly, to the conceptual framework of adjudication which was
inherited by the post-apartheid judiciary when constitutional democracy
dawned in 1994.
The conventional narrative about the South African judiciary was that
a liberal bench dominated South African jurisprudence until the mid
1950’s. It was then replaced by a pro-executive judiciary which deferred
with great jurisprudential gusto to the policies developed by the National
Party after its 1948 electoral victory. Of course, the earlier ‘liberal’
tradition was not entirely obliterated. It lived on in the judgments of a
small group of exceptionally courageous and principled judges. But the
hegemony was enjoyed by the executive-minded, so carefully appointed
by the government.
Expressed in its most elegant form, this clash of approaches to
adjudication was constituted between common-law judges who sought
to preserve the liberal values which justif‌ied the nature of the common
law and plain-fact judges who gave as wide a latitude to the output of
Parliament as was legally possible.
6
For this latter group of judges, it was
the law as it exists in fact which was determinative of their task to apply
the law. The ultimate source of law-as-fact was Parliament. By contrast,
those judges, who throughout the apartheid era strove to protect civil
liberties and the rule of law against an arbitrary and capricious legal
system introduced by the National Party, viewed law as not merely a
4
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996.
5
In particular see ss 8 and 39(2) of the Constitution .
6
The most penetrating scholarship in this f‌ield is by D Dyzenhaus Hard Cases in Wicked
Legal Systems: South African Law in the Perspective of Legal Philosophy (1991). See also D
Dyzenhaus ‘The disappearance of law’ (1990)107 SALJ 227.
220 DIGNITY,FREEDOM AND THE POST-APARTHEID LEGAL ORDER
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT