Towards a right to democratic governance in international law
Author | Udoka Ndidiamaka Owie |
DOI | 10.10520/EJC-c6be4aa6b |
Published date | 01 January 2016 |
Date | 01 January 2016 |
Record Number | sapr1_v31_n1_a2 |
Pages | 3-31 |
3
ARTICLE
TOWARDS A RIGHT TO DEMOCRATIC
GOVERNANCE IN INTERNATIONAL LAW
Udoka Ndidiamaka Owie*
ABSTRACT
In its classical positivist tradition international law was not concerned with the internal
structures of states, nor did it recognise the place of actors other than states; rather it
espoused the concept of domestic jurisdiction and non-interference in the domestic affairs
of states as evident in the Charter of the United Nations. Nevertheless, international law
has progressed from its traditional state-centrism to an acknowledgement of the place of
individuals in international law as highlighted by the development of the eld of human rights.
The aversion of traditional international law theorists to contemplate matters of purely
national law or constitutional law, such as how a government is formed, has been challenged
by the rise of democratic governments within state structures in Europe and Africa following
the end of the Cold War. With the articulation of a democratic entitlement to individuals in the
International Bill of Rights, as well as the aforementioned rise in democratic governments
and the work of the United Nations, regional organisations, civil society in democracy and
democratisation, a discourse on democratic governance has been inaugurated, opening
up international law to a consideration of matters of constitutional law, which hitherto were
uncharted waters.
1. INTRODUCTION
Traditionally, international law’s interest in the government of a state was limited with
regard to recognition, that is, to whether the government was in effective control to meet
the legal criteria for statehood or, where there has been a change of government extra-
constitutionally, to enable other states to determine the extent of their relations with
* LLB (Nig), BL (Nig), LLM (LSE), PhD (LSE) is a lecturer in Law at Baze University, Abuja and
currently a Visiting Scholar at Osgoode Hall School of Law, York University.
https://doi.org/10.25159/2219-6412/2650
ISSN 2219-6412 (Print)
© Unisa Press 2017
Southern African Public Law
https://upjournals.co.za/index.php/SAPL/index
Volume 31 | Number 1 | 2016 | pp. 3–31
4
Owie Towards a Right to Democratic Governance in International Law
such government.1 No attention was paid to whether a government was one that enjoyed
a popular mandate. Thus, ‘the fact that a particular government came into power by
military coup, through an uprising of parts of the population or through civil war was
irrelevant for the purpose of recognition.’2 Even at the San Francisco Conference,3
heralding the formation of the current international legal order, international law placed
a premium on the territorial sovereignty of states rather than the notion of popular
sovereignty, that is, the idea that the authority of a state is vested by the consent of
the governed through elected representatives. While including respect for the right
of self-determination of peoples in its purposes, the pervasive notion of sovereignty
encapsulated in the Charter of the United Nations (UN), as articulated as part of its
principles, is territorial sovereignty expressed in the inviolability of states and non-
intervention in domestic jurisdiction.4
This has resulted in the prevailing notion that international lawyers largely are
unconcerned about democracy, which they consider purely as a matter of constitutional
law. The aversion of traditional international law theorists to contemplate matters of a
purely national nature is reected in the view expressed by the American Law Institute
in 1987 that international law does not ‘generally address domestic constitutional
issues, such as how a national government is formed’.5 This view seems especially so
when considered against the background of the principle of respect for the domestic
jurisdiction of states.6
International law is dynamic and its involvement in democracy and democratic
governance is not epiphanic – it can be traced to the right of self-determination which
was instrumental in the process of de-colonisation. As a consequence of the development
of human rights towards the end of the rst half of the twentieth century, the articulation
1 See Montevideo Convention on the Rights and Duties of States 1933, 165 LNTS 19 Art 1; Tinoco
Claims Arbitration (Great Britain v Costa Rica), Decision of 18 October 1923, UNRIAA (1) 369.
It has, however, been asserted that the traditional criteria no longer sufce for an entity to achieve
statehood, see James Crawford, The Creation of States in International Law (2edn, Oxford University
Press 2006) 96–173. James Edmund Fawcett contended, in addition to the traditional criteria for the
recognition of a government of a new state, there is a requirement to respect the right of every citizen
to participate in the government of his country, directly or through representatives elected periodically
by equal and secret suffrage, see James Fawcett, ‘Security Council Resolutions on Rhodesia’ (1965–
1966) 41 British Yearbook of International Law 112; Obiora Chinedu Okafor, ‘The Global Process of
Legitimation and the Legitimacy of Global Governance’ (1997) 14 Arizona JICL 117 121–122.
2 Erika de Wet, ‘The Modern Practice of Intervention by Invitation in Africa and Its Implications for the
Prohibition of the Use of Force’ (2015) 26 European Journal of International Law (EJIL) 979 983.
3 UN,‘1945: The San Francisco Conference’ (UN) <www.un.org/en/sections/history-united-nations-
charter/1945-san-francisco-conference/index.html> accessed 15 April 2016.
4 1 UNTS XVI, art 2 (4) and art 2 (7).
5 American Law Institute, Restatement (Third) of the Foreign Relations Law of the United States, s
203, comment e (1987).
6 UN Charter (n 4) art 2 (7).
To continue reading
Request your trial