Needs, Rights and Transformation: Adjudicating Social Rights

JurisdictionSouth Africa
Pages5-36
Published date27 May 2019
Citation(2006) 17 Stell LR 5
Date27 May 2019
AuthorSandra Liebenberg
NEEDS, RIGHTS AND TRANSFORMATION:
ADJUDICATING SOCIAL RIGHTS
*
Sandra Liebenberg
BA LLB LLM
HF Oppenheimer Chair in Human Rights Law, University of Stellenbosch
1 Introduction
One of the most contested issues in South Africa’s burge oning
jurisprudence on social rights relates to how the courts should enforce
the duties imposed by these rights. Debate has focused in particular on
the extent to which the courts should affirm an enforceable right to the
provision of basic needs by those who lack access to these needs. In the
South African context, this is a plight affecting a substantial portion of
our population, and must also be contextualised within the high degree of
inequality existing in our society.
1
This article explores the relationship between a jurisprudence of basic
needs and the transformative goals of the Constitution. The question that
interests me is whether a jurisprudence relating to the fulfilment of social
and economic needs can have transformative potential, and if so, under
what conditions. My aim is to examine how such a perspective can
inform the development of our socio-economic rights jurisprudence in a
way that supports a project of social transformation consistent with
constitutional values and rights.
In the first part of the paper I draw on the work of philosopher and
political theorist, prof. Nancy Fraser, to examine the concepts of social
justice and transformation which are foundational to South Africa’s
constitutional project. The second part of the paper examines the specific
implications of the adjudication of social rights for pursuing a broader
project of social transformation and justice. The final section analyses
and evaluates the transformative potential of South Africa’s evolving
jurisprudence on socio-economic rights in the light of the theoretical
underpinnings I have developed.
* This article formed the basis for my inaugural lecture delivered on 4 October 2005 at the Law Faculty
of the University of Stellenbosch. I would like to thank Professors Andre
´van der Walt and Lourens du
Plessis for encouraging me to reflect on the theoretical dimensions of social rights adjudication. In
particular, I would like to thank Jan Theron for his critical perspectives and valuable comments.
1
See Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu-Natal 1997 12 BCLR 1696 (CC) par 8.
5
(2006) 17 Stell LR 5
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd
2 Social Justice, Transformation and ‘‘Non-reformist Reform’’
2 1 Social justice in a transformative Constitution
The South African Constitution is widely described as a transformative
Constitution.
2
Unlike many classic liberal constitutions, its primary
concern is not to restrain State power, but to facilitate a fundamental
change in unjust political, economic and social relations in South Africa.
3
Thus the preamble of the Constitution proclaims that it was adopted ‘‘so
as to — [h]eal the divisions of the past and establish a society based on
democratic values, social justice and fundamental human rights’’. The
founding values of the Constitution refer to ‘‘the achieveme nt of
equality’’, ‘‘non-racism and non-sexism’’, and a system of democratic
governance that is accountable, responsive and open.
4
The commitment to social justice is central to the transformative goals
and processes of our Constitution, and must infuse the interpretation of
the Bill of Rights. In the Fourth Bram Fischer Memorial Lecture, the
Chief Justice, Dikgang Moseneke,
5
describes the important role of social
justice in constitutional adjudication:
‘‘[I]t is argued here that a creative jurisprudence of equality coupled with substantive
interpretation of the content of ‘socio-economic’ rights should restore social justice as a
premier foundational value of our constitutional democracy side by side, if not interactively
with, human dignity, equality, freedom, accountability, responsiveness and openness.’’
By arguing that a conception of social justice should inform our
interpretation of rights claims, I am aligning myself with critical legal
theorists who argue that it is necessary ‘‘to step outside of’’ rights
discourse in order to fill rights with legal and institutional meaning.
6
I
2
Karl Klare ‘‘Legal Culture and Transformative Constitutionalism’’ 1998 SAJHR 146. Klare describes
transformative constitutionalism as ‘a’ long-term project of constitutional enactment, interpretation,
and enforcement committed (not in isolation, of course, but in a historical context of conducive
political developments) to transforming a country’s political and social institutions and power
relationships in a democratic, participatory, and egalitarian direction’’ (150). See Albertyn & Goldblatt
‘‘Facing the Challenges of Transformation: Difficulties in the Development of an Indigenous
Jurisprudence of Equality’’ 1998 SAJHR 248 249; Van der Walt ‘‘Tentative Urgency: Sensitivity for the
Paradoxes of Stability and Change in the Social Transformation Decisions of the Constitutional
Court’’ 2001 16 SA Public Law 1; Botha ‘‘Metaphoric Reasoning and Transformative Constitu-
tionalism’’ 2003 TSAR 20; Moseneke ‘‘Transformative Adjudication’’ 2002 18 SAJHR 309.
3
SvMakwanyane 1995 6 BCLR 665 (CC) par 262 (per Mahomed J); Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v
Minister of Environmental Affairs and Tourism 2004 7 BCLR 687 (CC); Minister of Finance v Van
Heerden 2004 11 BCLR 1125 (CC); Rates Action Group v City of Cape Town 2004 12 BCLR 1328 (C)
par 100.
4
S1.
5
2002 SAJHR 309 314. See also Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences v Hyundai Motor
Distributors (Pty) Ltd 2000 10 BCLR 1079 (CC) par 21; Government of the Republic of South Africa v
Grootboom 2000 11 BCLR 1169 (CC) par 1; Bel Porto School Governing Body v Premier, Western Cape
2002 9 BCLR 891 par 6; Minister of Finance v Van Heerden 2004 11 BCLR 1125 (CC) par 25; President
of RSA v Moddderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd 2005 8 BCLR 786 (CC) par 55.
6
Thus Klare ‘‘Legal Theory and Democratic Reconstruction: Reflections on 1989’’ 1991 25 UBC Law
Review 69 101 argues: ‘‘One must appeal to more concrete and therefore more controversial analyses of
the relevant social and institutional contexts than rights discourse offers; and one must develop and
elaborate conceptions of and intuitions about human freedom and self-determination by reference to
which one seeks to assess rights claims and resolve rights conflicts.’’
6 STELL LR 2006 1
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd
turn now to consider one theory of social justice and transformation that
I believe can assist in evaluating and developing our jurisprudence on
socio-economic rights.
2 2 Social justice as ‘‘participatory parity’’
Notions of social justice are of course highly contested in a pluralist
society. Any theory of social justice that is to do real work in interpreting
and adjudicating constitutional claims must be compatible with a
diversity of opinions regarding the good life. This is a pre-requisite in a
constitutional dispensation such as our own that takes seriously the equal
autonomy and moral worth of human beings.
7
At the same time, it must
supply sufficiently determinative criteria for adjudicating concrete cases.
Finally, it must be consonant with the values and ethos of the
Constitution.
Fraser
8
develops a theory of social justice based on the principle of
participatory parity. This principle recognises the right of all to
participate and interact with each other as peers in social life. As such
it is compatible with a plurality of different views of the good and ethical
disagreements. At the same time, she develops specific criteria for
assessing whether institutional arrangements accord people ‘‘the status of
full partners in social interaction’’.
9
Formal notions of equality are
rejected as insufficient. Instead, her theory focuses on the substantive
requirements to ensure that everyone has access to ‘‘the institutional
prerequisites of participatory parity’’, particularly the economic resources
and the social standing needed to participate on a par with others.
10
Fraser identifies two major obstacles to social justice conceived in
terms of promoting greater parity of participation in social life and
overcoming institutional patterns of subordination of different classes
and groups. The first, misrecognition, entails a form of status
subordination ‘‘in which institutionalized patterns of cultural value
impede parity of participation for some’’.
11
This involves systemic forms
of discrimination and disadvantaging of certain groups on grounds such
as race, gender and sexual orientation. Examples are marriage laws that
exclude same-sex partnerships, social-welfare policies that stigmatise
single mothers as sexually irresponsible scroungers, and policing practices
7
The recognition of the equal moral worth of people requires respect for difference and a diversity of
views and lifestyles: Prince v President, Cape Law Society 2002 2 SA 794 (CC): ‘‘The protection of
diversity is the hallmark of a free and open society. It is the recognition of the inherent dignity of all
human beings. Freedom is an indispensable ingredient of human dignity.’’ (per Ngcobo J par 49).
8
Justice Interruptus: Critical Reflections on the ‘‘Postsocialist’’ Condition (1997); ‘‘Rethinking
Recognition’’ 2000 3 New Left Review 107; Social Justice in the Age of Identity Politics: Redistribution,
Recognition and Participation in Fraser & Honneth Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-
Philosophical Exchange (2003).
9
Fraser Redistribution 229.
10
Participatory parity is described as constituting ‘‘a radical democratic interpretation of equal autonomy.
Far more demanding than standard liberal interpretations, this principle is not only deontological but
also substantive.’’ See Fraser Redistribution 229.
11
Fraser Redistribution 87.
NEEDS, RIGHTS AND TRANSFORMATION 7
© Juta and Company (Pty) Ltd

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT